1932

Abstract

Should legal rules be used to redistribute income? Or should income taxation be the exclusive means for reducing income inequality? This article reviews the legal scholarship on this question. First, it traces how the most widely cited argument in favor of using taxes exclusively—Kaplow & Shavell's (1994) double-distortion argument—evolved from previous debates about whether legal rules could even be redistributive and whether law and economics should be concerned exclusively with efficiency or with distribution as well. Next, it surveys the responses to the double-distortion argument. These responses appear to have had only limited success in challenging the sturdy reputation of the double-distortion argument. Finally, it highlights new directions in a debate revived by increasing economic inequality.

Loading

Article metrics loading...

/content/journals/10.1146/annurev-lawsocsci-101518-043037
2019-10-13
2024-03-28
Loading full text...

Full text loading...

/deliver/fulltext/lawsocsci/15/1/annurev-lawsocsci-101518-043037.html?itemId=/content/journals/10.1146/annurev-lawsocsci-101518-043037&mimeType=html&fmt=ahah

Literature Cited

  1. Ackerman B. 1971. Regulating slum housing markets on behalf of the poor: of housing codes, housing subsidies and income redistribution policy. Yale Law J 80:61093–197
    [Google Scholar]
  2. Adler M. 2012. Well-Being and Fair Distribution: Beyond Cost-Benefit Analysis Oxford, UK: Oxford Univ. Press
  3. Adler MD, Sanchirico CW. 2006. Inequality and uncertainty: theory and legal applications. Univ. Pa. Law Rev. 155:2279–377
    [Google Scholar]
  4. Alstott AL. 1999. Work versus freedom: a liberal challenge to employment subsidies. Yale Law J 108:5967–1058
    [Google Scholar]
  5. Alvaredo F, Atkinson AB, Piketty T, Saez E 2013. The top 1 percent in international and historical perspective. J. Econ. Perspect. 27:33–20
    [Google Scholar]
  6. Atkinson AB, Stiglitz JE. 1976. The design of tax structure: direct versus indirect taxation. J. Public Econ. 6:1–255–75
    [Google Scholar]
  7. Avraham R, Fortus D, Logue K 2004. Revisiting the roles of legal rules and tax rules in income redistribution: a response to Kaplow & Shavell. Iowa Law Rev 89:1125–58
    [Google Scholar]
  8. Ayres I. 2007. Market power and inequality: a competitive conduct standard for assessing when disparate impacts are unjustified. Calif. Law Rev. 95:3669–720
    [Google Scholar]
  9. Ayres I, Talley E. 1995. Solomonic bargaining: dividing a legal entitlement to facilitate Coasean trade. Yale Law J 104:51027–117
    [Google Scholar]
  10. Blumkin T, Margalioth Y. 2005. On the limits of redistributive taxation: establishing a case for equity-informed legal rules. Va. Tax Rev. 25:11–29
    [Google Scholar]
  11. Boadway R. 1997. Public economics and the theory of public policy. Can. J. Econ. 30:4a753–72
    [Google Scholar]
  12. Cahuc P, Zylberberg A. 2004. Labor Economics Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. , 1st ed..
  13. Calabresi G. 1991. The pointlessness of Pareto: carrying Coase further. Yale Law J 100:1211–37
    [Google Scholar]
  14. Coase RH. 1960. The problem of social cost. J. Law Econ. 3:1–44
    [Google Scholar]
  15. Coleman JL. 1979. Efficiency, utility, and wealth maximization. Hofstra Law Rev 8:509–51
    [Google Scholar]
  16. Cooter R, Ulen T. 2016. Law and Economics Boston: Addison-Wesley. , 6th ed..
  17. Craswell R. 1991. Passing on the costs of legal rules: efficiency and distribution in buyer-seller relationships. Stanford Law Rev 43:2361–98
    [Google Scholar]
  18. Craswell R. 2003. Kaplow and Shavell on the substance of fairness. J. Leg. Stud. 32:1245–75
    [Google Scholar]
  19. Dimick M. 2016. Should the law do anything about economic inequality?. Cornell J. Law Public Policy 26:1–69
    [Google Scholar]
  20. Dorff MB. 2001. Why welfare depends on fairness: a reply to Kaplow and Shavell. South. Calif. Law Rev. 75:847–900
    [Google Scholar]
  21. Eaton J, Rosen HS. 1980. Optimal redistributive taxation and uncertainty. Q. J. Econ. 95:2357–64
    [Google Scholar]
  22. Fennell LA, McAdams RH. 2016. The distributive deficit in law and economics. Minn. Law Rev. 100:1051–129
    [Google Scholar]
  23. Gamage D. 2014. How should governments promote distributive justice? A framework for analyzing the optimal choice of tax instruments. Tax Law Rev 68:1–87
    [Google Scholar]
  24. Gamage D. 2015. The case for taxing (all of) labor income, consumption, capital income, and wealth. Tax Law Rev 68:355–441
    [Google Scholar]
  25. Hale RL. 1923. Coercion and distribution in a supposedly non-coercive state. Political Sci. Q. 38:3470–94
    [Google Scholar]
  26. Hale RL. 1943. Bargaining, duress, and economic liberty. Columbia Law Rev 43:5603–28
    [Google Scholar]
  27. Hamada K. 1976. Liability rules and income distribution in product liability. Am. Econ. Rev. 66:1228–34
    [Google Scholar]
  28. Hasen D. 2006. Liberalism and ability taxation. Tex. Law Rev. 85:1057–113
    [Google Scholar]
  29. Hindriks J, Myles GD. 2013. Intermediate Public Economics Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
  30. Hsu S-L. 2014. The rise and rise of the one percent: considering the legal causes of wealth inequality. Emory Law J. Online 64:2043–72
    [Google Scholar]
  31. Hylland A, Zeckhauser R. 1979. Distributional objectives should affect taxes but not program choice or design. Scand. J. Econ. 81:2264–84
    [Google Scholar]
  32. Jolls C. 1998. Behavioral economics analysis of redistributive legal rules. Vanderbilt Law Rev 51:1653–77
    [Google Scholar]
  33. Kaplow L. 1995. A fundamental objection to tax equity norms: a call for utilitarianism. Natl. Tax J. 48:4497–514
    [Google Scholar]
  34. Kaplow L. 1996. The optimal supply of public goods and the distortionary cost of taxation. Natl. Tax J. 49:4513–33
    [Google Scholar]
  35. Kaplow L. 2006a. On the undesirability of commodity taxation even when income taxation is not optimal. J. Public Econ. 90:61235–50
    [Google Scholar]
  36. Kaplow L. 2006b. Public goods and the distribution of income. Eur. Econ. Rev. 50:71627–60
    [Google Scholar]
  37. Kaplow L. 2008. The Theory of Taxation and Public Economics Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press
  38. Kaplow L. 2012. On the choice of welfare standards in competition law. The Goals of Competition Law3–26 Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar
    [Google Scholar]
  39. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 1994. Why the legal system is less efficient than the income tax in redistributing income. J. Leg. Stud. 23:2667–81
    [Google Scholar]
  40. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 1999. The conflict between notions of fairness and the Pareto principle. Am. Law Econ. Rev. 1:163–77
    [Google Scholar]
  41. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 2000a. Notions of fairness versus the Pareto principle: on the role of logical consistency. Yale Law J 110:2237–49
    [Google Scholar]
  42. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 2000b. Should legal rules favor the poor? Clarifying the role of legal rules and the income tax in redistributing income. J. Leg. Stud. 29:2821–35
    [Google Scholar]
  43. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 2001a. Any non-welfarist method of policy assessment violates the Pareto principle. J. Political Econ. 109:2281–86
    [Google Scholar]
  44. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 2001b. Fairness versus welfare. Harvard Law Rev 114:961–1388
    [Google Scholar]
  45. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 2003. Fairness versus welfare: notes on the Pareto principle, preferences, and distributive justice. J. Leg. Stud. 32:1331–62
    [Google Scholar]
  46. Kaplow L, Shavell S. 2009. Fairness versus Welfare Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press
  47. Kelman M. 1987. A Guide to Critical Legal Studies Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press
  48. Kennedy D. 1981. Distributive and paternalist motives in contract and tort law, with special reference to compulsory terms and unequal bargaining power. Md. Law Rev. 41:4563–658
    [Google Scholar]
  49. Kennedy D. 1987. The effect of the warranty of habitability on low income housing: ‘milking’ and class violence. Fla. State Univ. Law Rev. 15:485–519
    [Google Scholar]
  50. Kennedy D. 1991. The stakes of law, or Hale and Foucault! Leg. Stud. Forum 15:327–66
    [Google Scholar]
  51. Kennedy D. 1998. Law and economics from the perspective of critical legal studies. The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law 2 P Newman 465–74 New York: Stockton
    [Google Scholar]
  52. Kleinbard ED. 2017. Capital taxation in an age of inequality. South. Calif. Law Rev. 90:3593–682
    [Google Scholar]
  53. Komesar NK. 1973. Return to Slumville: a critique of the Ackerman analysis of housing code enforcement and the poor. Yale Law J 82:61175–93
    [Google Scholar]
  54. Komesar NK. 1984. Revolution in landlord-tenant law: a comparative institutional view. Cornell Law Rev 69:612–22
    [Google Scholar]
  55. Kornhauser LA. 2003. Preference, well-being, and morality in social decisions. J. Leg. Stud. 32:1303–29
    [Google Scholar]
  56. Kwak J. 2015. Reducing inequality with a retrospective tax on capital. Cornell J. Law Public Policy 25:191–244
    [Google Scholar]
  57. Lewinsohn-Zamir D. 2006. In defense of redistribution through private law. Minn. Law Rev. 91:326–97
    [Google Scholar]
  58. Lindbeck A, Weibull JW. 1987. Balanced-budget redistribution as the outcome of political competition. Public Choice 52:3273–97
    [Google Scholar]
  59. Liscow Z. 2014. Reducing inequality on the cheap: when legal rule design should incorporate equity as well as efficiency. Yale Law J 123:72478–510
    [Google Scholar]
  60. Markovits RS. 1976. The distributive impact, allocative efficiency, and overall desirability of ideal housing codes: some theoretical clarifications. Harvard Law Rev 89:1815–46
    [Google Scholar]
  61. Markovits RS. 2004. Why Kaplow and Shavell's double-distortion argument articles are wrong. George Mason Law Rev 13:511–619
    [Google Scholar]
  62. McCaffery EJ. 2005. A new understanding of tax. Mich. Law Rev. 103:5807–938
    [Google Scholar]
  63. Meltzer AH, Richard SF. 1981. A rational theory of the size of government. J. Political Econ. 89:5914–27
    [Google Scholar]
  64. Mirrlees JA. 1990. Taxing uncertain incomes. Oxford Econ. Pap. 42:134–45
    [Google Scholar]
  65. Musgrave RA. 1959. The Theory of Public Finance: A Study in Public Economy New York: McGraw-Hill
  66. Piketty T. 2014. Capital in the Twenty-First Century Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univ. Press
  67. Piketty T, Saez E. 2003. Income inequality in the United States, 1913–1998. Q. J. Econ. 118:11–41
    [Google Scholar]
  68. Polinsky AM. 1989. An Introduction to Law and Economics New York: Aspen Pub. , 2nd ed..
  69. Posner RA. 1979. The ethical and political basis of the efficiency norm in common law adjudication. Hofstra Law Rev 8:487–507
    [Google Scholar]
  70. Posner RA. 1985. Wealth maximization revisited. Notre Dame J. Law Ethics Public Policy 2:85–105
    [Google Scholar]
  71. Rabin EH. 1983. Revolution in residential landlord-tenant law: causes and consequences. Cornell Law Rev 69:517–84
    [Google Scholar]
  72. Rawls J. 1999. A Theory of Justice Oxford, UK: Oxford Univ. Press
  73. Saez E. 2002. The desirability of commodity taxation under non-linear income taxation and heterogeneous tastes. J. Public Econ. 83:2217–30
    [Google Scholar]
  74. Sanchirico CW. 2000a. Deconstructing the new efficiency rationale. Cornell Law Rev 86:1003–89
    [Google Scholar]
  75. Sanchirico CW. 2000b. Taxes versus legal rules as instruments for equity: a more equitable view. J. Leg. Stud. 29:2797–820
    [Google Scholar]
  76. Sanchirico CW. 2010. A critical look at the economic argument for taxing only labor income. Tax Law Rev 63:867–956
    [Google Scholar]
  77. Sanchirico CW. 2011. Tax eclecticism. Tax Law Rev 64:149–227
    [Google Scholar]
  78. Schwab S. 1989. Coase defends Coase: why lawyers listen and economists do not. Mich. Law Rev. 87:61171–98
    [Google Scholar]
  79. Segal I, Whinston MD. 2014. The efficiency of bargaining under divided entitlements. Univ. Chicago Law Rev. 81:1273–89
    [Google Scholar]
  80. Shavell S. 1980. Strict liability versus negligence. J. Leg. Stud. 9:11–25
    [Google Scholar]
  81. Shavell S. 1981. A note on efficiency versus distributional equity in legal rulemaking: Should distributional equity matter given optimal income taxation?. Am. Econ. Rev. 71:2414–18
    [Google Scholar]
  82. Stark KJ. 2005. Enslaving the beachcomber: some thoughts on the liberty objections to endowment taxation. Can. J. Law Jurisprud. 18:147–68
    [Google Scholar]
  83. Stiglitz JE. 1987. Pareto efficient and optimal taxation and the new welfare economics. Handbook of Public Economics 2 AJ Auerbach, M Feldstein 991–1042 Amsterdam: Elsevier
    [Google Scholar]
  84. Varian HR. 1980. Redistributive taxation as social insurance. J. Public Econ. 14:149–68
    [Google Scholar]
  85. Waldron J. 2003. Locating distribution. J. Leg. Stud. 32:1277–302
    [Google Scholar]
  86. Weisbach DA. 2003. Should legal rules be used to redistribute income. Univ. Chicago Law Rev. 70:1439–53
    [Google Scholar]
  87. Williamson OE. 1968. Economies as an antitrust defense: the welfare tradeoffs. Am. Econ. Rev. 58:118–36
    [Google Scholar]
  88. Zelenak L. 2006. Taxing endowment. Duke Law J 55:1145–81
    [Google Scholar]
/content/journals/10.1146/annurev-lawsocsci-101518-043037
Loading
  • Article Type: Review Article
This is a required field
Please enter a valid email address
Approval was a Success
Invalid data
An Error Occurred
Approval was partially successful, following selected items could not be processed due to error