1932

Abstract

Evidence from a number of research methods converges to suggest that when a person registers a transgression against self or others, the person experiences an intuitively produced, emotionally tinged reaction of moral outrage. The reaction is driven by the just deserts–based retributive reactions of the person to the transgression rather than, for instance, considerations of the deterrent force of the punishment. In experimental games arranged so that trust and fairness transgressions occur, participants punish transgressors and experience rewarding brain states while doing so, and they punish even if they were not themselves the target of the violation. What, if any, implications does this have for the punishment component of societal systems of justice? Would it be possible to construct sentencing practices that, to some extent, incorporated citizens’ sense of just punishments? What would be gained by doing so? And what would be lost?

Loading

Article metrics loading...

/content/journals/10.1146/annurev.lawsocsci.4.110707.172335
2009-12-01
2024-10-11
Loading full text...

Full text loading...

/deliver/fulltext/lawsocsci/5/1/annurev.lawsocsci.4.110707.172335.html?itemId=/content/journals/10.1146/annurev.lawsocsci.4.110707.172335&mimeType=html&fmt=ahah

Literature Cited

  1. Alter AL, Kernochan J, Darley JM. 2007. Transgression wrongfulness outweighs its harmfulness as a determinant of sentence severity. Law Hum. Behav. 31:319–35 [Google Scholar]
  2. Anderson D. 2002. The deterrence hypothesis and picking pockets at the pickpocket's hanging. Am. Law Econ. Rev. 4:2295–313 [Google Scholar]
  3. Benton L. 2002. Law and Colonial Cultures: Legal Regimes in World History, 1400–1900 Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Univ. Press [Google Scholar]
  4. Cannon L. 1999. Official Negligence: How Rodney King and the Riots Changed Los Angeles and the LAPD Boulder, CO: Westview. Paperback ed. [Google Scholar]
  5. Carlsmith KM. 2006. The roles of retribution and utility in determining punishment. J. Exp. Soc. Psychol. 4:4437–51 [Google Scholar]
  6. Carlsmith KM, Darley JM, Robinson PH. 2002. Why do we punish? Deterrence and just deserts as motives for punishment. J. Personal. Soc. Psychol. 2:83284–99 [Google Scholar]
  7. Cooksey RW. 1996. Judgment Analysis: Theory, Methods, and Applications San Diego, CA: Academic [Google Scholar]
  8. Darley JM, Carlsmith KM, Robinson PH. 2000. Incapacitation and just deserts as motives for punishment. Law Hum. Behav. 24:659–83 [Google Scholar]
  9. Darley JM, Carlsmith KM, Robinson PH. 2001. The ex ante function of the criminal law. Law Soc. Rev. 35:701–26 [Google Scholar]
  10. de Quervain DJF, Fischbacher U, Treyer V, Schellhammer M, Schnyder U. et al. 2004. The neural basis of altruistic punishment. Science 305:56881254–58 [Google Scholar]
  11. Doob AN, Webster CM. 2003. Sentence severity and crime: accepting the null hypothesis. Crime and Justice: A Review of Research M Tonry 30143–95 Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press [Google Scholar]
  12. Fehr E, Fischbacher U. 2004. Third-party punishment and social norms. Evol. Hum. Behav. 25:263–87 [Google Scholar]
  13. Garland D. 1990. Punishment and Modern Society: A Study in Social Theory Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press [Google Scholar]
  14. Greene JD, Cushman F, Stewart L, Lowenberg K, Nystrom LE, Cohen JD. 2009. Pushing moral buttons: the interaction between personal force and intention in moral judgment. Cognition 111:3364–71 [Google Scholar]
  15. Greene JD, Nystrom LE, Engell AD, Darley JM, Cohen JD. 2004. The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron 44:389–400 [Google Scholar]
  16. Greene JD, Sommerville RB, Nystrom LE, Darley JM, Cohen JD. 2001. An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science 293:2105–8 [Google Scholar]
  17. Gromet DM. 2009. Restoration and retribution: people's negotiation of multiple responses to wrongdoing PhD diss Princeton Univ. Princeton, NJ: [Google Scholar]
  18. Gromet DM, Darley JM. 2006. Restoration and retribution: how including retributive components affects the acceptability of restorative justice procedures. Soc. Justice Res. 19:395–432 [Google Scholar]
  19. Gromet DM, Darley JM. 2009. Punishment and beyond: achieving justice through the satisfaction of multiple goals. Law Soc. Rev. 43:1–38 [Google Scholar]
  20. Gürerk O, Irlenbusch B, Rockenbach B. 2006. The competitive advantage of sanctioning institutions. Science 312:108–11 [Google Scholar]
  21. Haidt J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol. Rev. 108:814–34 [Google Scholar]
  22. Hardin G. 1968. The tragedy of the commons. Science 162:1243–48 [Google Scholar]
  23. Hart HLA. 1948–1949. The ascription of responsibility and rights. Proc. Aristot. Soc. 49:171–94 [Google Scholar]
  24. Hauser M, Cushman F, Young L, Kang-Xing J, Mikhail J. 2007. A dissociation between moral judgments and justifications. Mind Lang. 22:1–21 [Google Scholar]
  25. Heider F. 1958. The Psychology of Interpersonal Relations Hoboken, NJ: Wiley326 [Google Scholar]
  26. Henrich J, McElreath R, Barr A, Ensminger J, Barrett C. et al. 2006. Costly punishment across human societies. Science 312:57811767–70 [Google Scholar]
  27. Kahneman D. 2003. A perspective on judgment and choice: mapping bounded rationality. Am. Psychol. 58:697–720 [Google Scholar]
  28. Kahneman D, Knetsch JL, Thaler RH. 1986. Fairness and the assumptions of economics. J. Bus. 59:S285–300 [Google Scholar]
  29. Mikhail J. 2007. Universal moral grammar: theory, evidence and the future. Trends Cogn. Sci. 11:143–52 [Google Scholar]
  30. Miller DT. 2001. Disrespect and the experience of injustice. Annu. Rev. Psychol. 52:527–53 [Google Scholar]
  31. Much NC, Shweder RA. 1978. Speaking of rules: the analysis of culture in breach. New Dir. Child Dev. Soc. Cogn. 219–39 [Google Scholar]
  32. Nadler J. 2005. Flouting the law. Tex. Law Rev. 83:1399–441 [Google Scholar]
  33. Napier J, Tyler T. 2008. Does moral conviction really override concerns about procedural justice? A reexamination of the value protection model. Soc. Justice Res. 21:509–28 [Google Scholar]
  34. Nisbett RE, Wilson TD. 1977. Telling more than we can know: verbal reports on mental processes. Psychol. Rev. 84:231–59 [Google Scholar]
  35. Robinson PH, Darley J. 1997. The utility of desert. Northwest. Univ. Law Rev. 91:453–99 [Google Scholar]
  36. Robinson PH, Darley J. 2007. Intuitions of justice: implications for criminal law and justice policy. South. Calif. Law Rev. 81:1–67 [Google Scholar]
  37. Robinson P, Kurzban R. 2007. Concordance and conflict in intuitions of justice. Minn. Law Rev. 91:1829–907 [Google Scholar]
  38. Robinson PH, Kurzban R, Jones OD. 2007. The origins of shared institutions of justice. Vanderbilt Law Rev. 60:61633–88 [Google Scholar]
  39. Rosenmerkel SP. 2001. Wrongfulness and harmfulness as components of seriousness of white-collar offenses. J. Contemp. Crim. Justice 17:308–27 [Google Scholar]
  40. Sanfey AG, Rilling JK, Aronson JA, Nystrom LE, Cohen JD. 2003. The neural basis of economic decision making in the ultimatum game. Science 300:1755–60 [Google Scholar]
  41. Simon J. 2007. Governing Through Crime: How the War on Crime Transformed American Democracy and Created a Culture of Fear New York: Oxford Univ. Press [Google Scholar]
  42. Skitka LJ. 2002. Do the means always justify the ends, or do the ends sometimes justify the means? A value protection model of justice reasoning. Personal. Soc. Psychol. Bull. 28:5588–97 [Google Scholar]
  43. Sloman SA. 1996. The empirical case for two systems of reasoning. Psychol. Bull. 119:3–22 [Google Scholar]
  44. Sloman SA. 2002. Two systems of reasoning. Heuristics and Biases T Gilovich, D Griffin, D Kahneman 379–96 New York: Cambridge Univ. Press [Google Scholar]
  45. Stanovich KE, West RF. 2002. Individual differences in reasoning: implications for the rationality debate. Heuristics and Biases T Gilovich, D Griffin, D Kahneman 421–40 New York: Cambridge Univ. Press [Google Scholar]
  46. Tversky A, Kahneman D. 1983. Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychol. Rev. 90:293–315 [Google Scholar]
  47. Tyler TR. 1990. Why People Obey the Law New Haven, CT: Yale Univ. Press [Google Scholar]
  48. Tyler TR, Huo Y. 2002. Trust in the Law New York: Russell Sage Found. [Google Scholar]
  49. van den Haag E. 1987. Punishment: desert and crime control. Mich. Law Rev. 85:1250 [Google Scholar]
  50. Walton MD, Sedlak AJ. 1982. Making amends: a grammar-based analysis of children's social interaction. Merrill-Palmer Q. 28:389–412 [Google Scholar]
  51. Warr M. 1989. What is the perceived seriousness of crimes?. Criminology 27:795–821 [Google Scholar]
  52. Wasik M, von Hirsch A. 1990. Statutory sentencing principles: the 1990 white paper. Mod. Law Rev. 53:508–17 [Google Scholar]
  53. Young L, Cushman F, Hauser M, Saxe R. 2007. The neural basis of the interaction between theory of mind and moral judgment. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 104:8235–40 [Google Scholar]
/content/journals/10.1146/annurev.lawsocsci.4.110707.172335
Loading
  • Article Type: Review Article
This is a required field
Please enter a valid email address
Approval was a Success
Invalid data
An Error Occurred
Approval was partially successful, following selected items could not be processed due to error